\n Nicholas F. Gier, Department of Philosophy, University of
\n Idaho, Moscow, ID 83844-3016 (ngier\u2202<\/span><\/span>uidaho.edu<\/a>)<\/span><\/p>\n
\n from Gandhi Marg <\/i>23:3 (October-December, 2001), pp.
\n 261-284 <\/span><\/p>\n
\n Permission to link article given by Mahendra
\n Kumar, coeditor of Gandhi Marg<\/i><\/span><\/p>\n
\n\n Note: Some endnotes may be incomplete or
\n missing, and the argument for nonviolence as an enabling virtue has been
\n rejected in the final version in The Virtue of Non-Violence: from Gautama
\n to Gandhi <\/i>(SUNY Press, 2004), chap. 9.<\/span><\/p>\n<\/blockquote>\n
\n <\/b><\/p>\n\n The following essay is the main chapter of a book manuscript
\n entitled "The Virtue of Non-Violence: from Gautama to Gandhi." The book attempts to
\n accomplish two principal goals: (1) to conceive of nonviolence
\n from the standpoint of virtue ethics; and (2) to give Gandhi’s philosophy a
\n Buddhist interpretation. My intent is not to foreclose on the possibility of
\n a Hindu or Jain reading of Gandhi’s work; rather, I argue that there are some
\n distinct advantages in thinking of Gandhi as a Buddhist.
\n Writing to a Burmese friend in
\n 1919, Gandhi said that "when . . . I became acquainted with the teaching of
\n the Buddha, my eyes were opened to the limitless possibilities of
\n nonviolence"; and he also said that the "Buddha taught us to defy appearances
\n and trust in the final triumph of Truth and Love."[1]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/a>
\n Although Gandhi’s neo-Vedantism is more compatible with Mahayana Buddhism, I
\n will propose that the ethics of nonviolence works better with a Pali Buddhist
\n view of the self and world. This essay will focus on the first goal of
\n explicating a virtue theory of nonviolence.<\/span><\/p>\n\n My task is not to give a full scale defense of virtue ethics,
\n but I have appropriated the thoughts of the best virtue theorists, have added
\n my own insights, and have applied then to Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n ethics. Some of Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n ideas cannot be forced into this theoretical framework, so that means that
\n Vedantist or theistic rule ethics are also options. Furthermore, Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n commitment to the Indian ascetic tradition and to a Hindu dialectic of
\n extremes is not compatible with either the Buddhist Middle Way or the
\n moderation of classical virtue theory. Hindus are sometimes prone to, as
\n Wendy Doniger describes it, to pursue a Doctrine of Golden Extremes, between
\n excessive eroticism at one end and excessive asceticism at the other.[2]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n The more contemporary Gandhians stress this aspect of Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n philosophy the more difficult it will be to build an acceptable theory of
\n nonviolent political activism that all people can embrace.<\/p>\nRULES AND
\n VIRTUES<\/b><\/div>\n\n\n When one thinks of the question "<\/span>Which came
\n first–moral rules or virtues?"<\/span>
\n the obvious answer, I contend, is that virtues came first. Moral imperatives
\n are abstractions from thousands of years of observing loyal, honest, patient,
\n just, and compassionate behavior, just as moral prohibitions have come from
\n equally ancient experiences with the vices. There is good evidence to argue
\n that the expression of moral rules requires a spoken language and one could argue just
\n as persuasively that virtues manifested themselves in prelinguistic
\n human beings. For example, strong circumstantial evidence for compassion among
\n the Neanderthals can be joined with the hypothesis that their very high larynx
\n made it impossible to articulate the basic vowels.[3]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Michael Spangle and Kent Menzel state that "<\/span>spoken language
\n transformed our species and was a major factor in forging the human world as
\n we know it."<\/span>[4]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n They also argue for the existence of an
\n A<\/span>acoustic trigger to
\n conceptualization@<\/span>
\n that gestural language obviously lacks. While there is now a consensus that
\n gestures are integral to all natural languages (remarkably, even the blind
\n gesture when they speak), it is generally agreed that they do not express abstractions very well
\n at all. <\/p>\n\n\n It is even more clear that divine virtues precede divine law,
\n because God=<\/span>s virtues
\n would remain even if God chose not to create a world. The Pauline view that
\n the Law was created only to manifest human sin further proves its contingency
\n and confirms the idea of a "<\/span>lawless"<\/span>
\n God before creation. For medieval nominalism the moral law characterizes what
\n God has ordained (potentia ordinata<\/i>) for a sinful world, and it is not
\n part of God=<\/span>s
\n potentia absoluta<\/i>. Even though Aquinas maintains that there is practical
\n as well as theoretical reason in GodB<\/span>s<\/span>pecifically
\n God would know the rule that good always excludes evilB<\/span>this
\n argument is open to serious objections. Furthermore, Gandhi speaks of God=<\/span>s
\n laws frequently and if he believes those laws are part of the nature of God,
\n then a Gandhian virtue ethics is not possible.<\/p>\n\n <\/p>\n
\n Philosopher Leslie Stephen describes virtue ethics as follows:
\n "Morality is internal. The moral law. . . has to be expressed in the form,
\n ‘be this,’ not in the form ‘do this.’ . . . The true moral law says ‘hate
\n not,’ instead of ‘kill not.’ . . . The only mode of stating the moral law must
\n be as a rule of character."[5]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n In other words, people of good character and virtue require no reminder of
\n what the rules are or what their duty is. For John Stuart Mill the application of internal sanctions had much more moral value than the
\n imposition of external sanctions, those that most often used by parents and
\n societies to control human behavior. Mill=<\/span>s
\n argument is persuasive: a society living under self-imposed vows would require
\n few police, judges, and prisons thereby maximizing utility. Generally
\n speaking, the sanctions for virtue ethics are internal and self-regulating,
\n whereas the sanctions for rule ethics, especially in its religious form, are
\n external. (Kant joins virtue ethics in favoring internal sanctions.) For the
\n Greeks, the Roman Stoics, Buddhists, and the Confucians, virtue was its own
\n reward, but for most Christians, the incentive for good deeds is eternal life
\n in heaven, with eternal damnation for those who do not follow the rules.<\/div>\n\n\n <\/p>\n
\n One of the problems with rule ethics is applying the rules to
\n specific cases. The imperatives of virtue ethics–be patient, be kind, be
\n generous, be compassionate, be courageous–better equip an individual to
\n negotiate the obstacles of the moral life. The virtue ethics approach is not
\n to follow a set of abstract rules, but to develop an ensemble of behaviors,
\n dispositions, and qualities that lead to human excellence and the good life.
\n Virtue ethics may not have pat answers to specific cases–no ethical theory
\n could offer this–but it does prepare the moral agent for adaptation,
\n innovation, and self-discovery. As Martha Nussbaum states:
\n A<\/span>The good agent must
\n therefore cultivate the ability to perceive and correctly describe his or her
\n situation finely and truly, including in this perceptual grasp even those
\n features of the situation that are not covered under the existing rule.@<\/span>[6]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>\n <\/p>\n\n Annette Baier=<\/span>s
\n analysis of trust is a good example of the specific adaptability of the
\n virtues.[7]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Rule based ethics and its contractarian social and political arrangements give
\n the false impression that the essence of the moral life consists of conforming
\n to general rules. Obeying rules can be made specific in a legal contract, but
\n it would of course be impossible to cover the exigencies of our lives with
\n such formal arrangements. It is the virtue of trust that is basic to human
\n interactions and only a few of the myriad promises necessary for the smooth
\n running of human life could ever be spelled out in contract form. It would be
\n not only be absurd but also a great insult to plumbers (Baier=<\/span>s
\n hilarious example) to A<\/span>having
\n it in writing@<\/span> that
\n they promise not to plant explosives in the pipes of the houses they visit.
\n Again it is the virtues that come first and they are the tools the do the work
\n of the moral life. As Martha Nussbaum so aptly states:
\n A<\/span>A good rule is a good
\n summary of wise particular choices and not a court of last resort. Like rules
\n in medicine and in navigation, ethical rules should be held open to
\n modification in the light of new circumstances@<\/span>[8]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a><\/div>\n\n\n <\/p>\n
\n Interestingly enough, some virtuous behavior is not always
\n required in cases that might call for it, while confirmation to rules demands
\n no exceptions. For example, generous people do not lose their virtue if they
\n do not give to all charities as a
\n A<\/span>rule to give@<\/span>
\n might command or certainly what Peter Singer requires for maximum world-wide
\n utility. Let us imagine a burning house where a hedonic calculator is
\n indicating that it is too dangerous to go in and save the children inside.
\n While all utilitarians would be bound by the calculus and all Kantians would
\n be bound by the rule that it is always irrational to go beyond one=<\/span>s
\n duty, virtue theory would allow people to act on their own personal mean
\n between cowardice and foolhardiness. Turning to yet another virtue, it is
\n clear that even the virtue of justice always amounts to more than simply
\n conforming to the strict letter of the law. The craft excellence of judicial
\n review, as well as daily extralegal decisions, always lead to unique,
\n distinctive, and noncompulsory results.<\/p>\n\n <\/p>\n
\n Another way to demonstrate the superiority of virtues over
\n rules is to think of the life of the consummate couch potato. (This is very apt,
\n as I come from a state that is famous for its potatoes.) He is a man
\n who essentially lives and works on his couch. His job is entering data via
\n a
\n modem attached to his computer. It does not take much thinking to enter the
\n data, so he is able to view his favorite TV shows all the time. His
\n refrigerator and microwave, of course, are handy for snacks, drinks, and
\n frozen dinners. Our sofa slug is also a very religious person. He tunes into
\n to his favorite TV preachers on Sunday morning and sends in his tithes by
\n mail. Finally, let us say that this man has never broken a law or committed
\n a
\n sin in his life. According to Aristotle, such a life lacks virtually
\n everything that counts as human excellence; and for Confucius, this man
\n remains very much an uncut gem. Our couch potato obeys all moral laws, but he
\n does not aspire to cultivate the virtues of the good life. According to rule
\n ethics and traditional religion, however, this man is fully moral, and,
\n assuming divine favor, saved as well. Bernard Mayo clearly sees the
\n implications of this example: "People might well have no moral qualities
\n at
\n all except the possession of principles and the will (and capacity) to act
\n accordingly."[9]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n This appears to be a severe indictment for any rule-based ethics.<\/div>\n\n\n As we have seen, the sanctions of a rule-based ethics, in its
\n religious form, are primarily external: rewards for those who do good and
\n punishment for those who do evil. This may lead to a mere moralism rather
\n than a genuine morality based on internal sanctions and the view that virtue
\n is its own reward. Most people would agree that the latter is a more
\n admirable form of ethical motivation, and we have seen that internal sanctions
\n maximize utility. Most traditional religious ethics teaches us the wrong
\n reasons to be moral. We should become moral so as to become a better person
\n and be an example to others, rather than for the purely selfish reasons of avoiding punishment. Moral
\n action should flow naturally from our selves; we
\n should not have to be bribed to be moral. Justice will not be achieved by
\n following rules, it will only be attained, as Plato, Confucius, the Buddha,
\n and Gandhi envisioned, by people with balanced and harmonious souls and the
\n particular just acts that comes from such harmony. <\/p>\n\n Another concern about duty ethics is the problem of legalism.
\n True morality should be the foundation of law, and the virtues, as prior to
\n law, would then serve as a guide and check to any law. Humans acted
\n courageously, justly, beneficently before they laid down rules regulating
\n human behavior. A rule-based ethics reverses this order. It speaks of law,
\n usually divine law, first, and moral rules come directly from the mind and
\n mouth of the lawgiver. But true morality must always serve as a check for the
\n possibility of unjust laws. If law and morality are the same, then this
\n crucial idea of morality as the guardian of just law is undermined. For
\n example, most of my students are able to condemn Zeus and other Greek gods as
\n immoral deities because of the basic intuition, central to virtue ethics, that
\n virtue precedes law. The king, earthly or heavenly, is not always right,
\n and
\n we must always guard against the false identity of the legislator and the
\n source of the Good.<\/p><\/div>\n\n\n Yet another problem is the issue is freedom. For Kant a duty
\n is whatever one is forced to do according to the moral law, and the moral will
\n lives by the dictates of reason. This does not sound like freedom at all. If
\n the will is truly free, it must be free from reason as well. (Although virtue
\n theory steers clear of all dichotomies, it is clear that it would be a form of
\n moral voluntarism.) For Kant the consistently autonomous person would be one
\n who can no longer choose the wrong and must always choose the right. (This
\n seems to be the implication in Platonic ethics as well.) Virtue ethics,
\n however, is free from these conundrums of moral rationalism. <\/p>\n\n For Aristotle the virtues are dispositions that we freely
\n choose to develop, and everyday we have to fine tune the moral means that are
\n relative to us and our situations. (It is true that after a short while the
\n virtues become habits [ethike<\/i>], but we are still fully responsible for
\n actions that proceed from them.) Rule morality recognizes no middle way
\n and
\n no variation on an absolute right. Virtue ethics always aims at a personal
\n mean that is a creative choice for each individual. Such an approach engages
\n the imagination and personalizes and intensifies moral responsibility. While
\n there can be no process of self-discovery in duty ethics, virtue ethics
\n requires us to confront a growing, dynamic self in ever changing conditions.
\n Here again is the reason for the dynamic Buddhist self as opposed to the
\n universal static self of Hinduism and Stoicism.<\/div>\n\n<\/p>\n
VIRTUE AND
\n VIRILITY<\/b><\/p>\n\n In the ancient world virtue was thoroughly gendered. There was
\n a strong connection between self-mastery, freedom, and virility. (The Latin
\n virtus<\/i> stems from vir<\/i> meaning
\n A<\/span>manhood@<\/span>
\n so that Roman virtue meant A<\/span>excellence
\n of manly qualities.@<\/span>)
\n Aristotle=<\/span>s conception
\n of woman as an ill formed and irrational man was almost universally accepted.
\n Lacking reason the woman could not instill reason in those things without it,
\n which of course the virtuous man could. (This meant that the virtuous man
\n could control his sexual appetites, but women in general could not.)
\n Greco-Roman ethics was, according to Foucault, an
\n A<\/span>ethics of men made
\n for men, . . . a structure of virility that related oneself to oneself.@<\/span>10<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a><\/div>\n\n\n Foucault also demonstrates that there was a close alliance
\n among sexual virility, ethical virility, and social virility. The social
\n hierarchy of virility and mastery produced interesting anomalies, such as the
\n wife of the house being more masculine than the male slaves. Here the virtuous
\n wife has these qualities only because she has imitated male self-mastery.
\n Foucault gives the example of Ischomachus=<\/span>
\n wife in Zenophon=<\/span>s
\n Oeconomicus <\/i>who displays
\n A<\/span>masculine understanding@<\/span>
\n and is so well trained by her husband that she, like Plutarch=<\/span>s
\n barking dog, need hear his commands only once.11<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Fourth Maccabees<\/i>, a Hellenistic Jewish text, portrays the brave mother
\n of seven boys as more masculine than Antiochus Epiphanes, the tyrant who
\n tortures her sons to death.[12]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a> \n <\/p>\n\n\n Interestingly enough, the only Hindu god who is allowed to be
\n depicted with muscles is the celibate Hanuman, the patron god of wrestlers.
\n Hanuman always preserves his tejas<\/i>, the power of the male gods. (Virya<\/i>,
\n linked to the Latin virtus,<\/i> is another Sanskrit word for male power,
\n with its meanings of manliness, heroism, and male seed.) Tejas<\/i> is not
\n only an attribute of the gods and antigods (asuras<\/i>), but it is also
\n found in the Manus, sages, priests, kings, and ordinary men. The priest "takes
\n on a physical form of brilliant energy (tejas<\/i>) and attains the supreme
\n condition . . . A<\/span>; the
\n king is "made from particles of these lords and gods, therefore he surpasses
\n all living beings in brilliant energy (tejas<\/i>)."[13]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Tejas<\/i> ebbs and flows, as can be seen in the man who breaks a vow of
\n chastity, sheds his semen, and loses his tejas<\/i> back to the gods. Also
\n significant is the case of the man who loses his tejas<\/i> by having sex
\n with a menstruating woman, and the priest who loses his vitality by looking at
\n a woman "putting on her eye make-up, rubbing oil on herself, undressed, or
\n giving birth.[14]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Even in their misogyny the author(s) of the Laws of Manu<\/i> give a
\n back-handed compliment to the power of woman.<\/p>\n\n Initially one=<\/span>s
\n impression of Gandhi is that he conforms to this traditional fusion of virtue
\n and virility. In fact, commentators have said that one of Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n greatest achievements was the he destroyed the Orientialist prejudice that the
\n West was masculine and the East was feminineB<\/span>summed
\n up aptly in John Strachey’s description of the Bengalis=<\/span>"extraordinary effeminancy.@<\/span>[15]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Much of Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n rhetoric has strong martial overtones: such as
\n A<\/span>nonviolent warfare@<\/span>
\n waged with the A<\/span>masculine
\n virtues@<\/span>; and
\n "nonviolence. . . does not mean cowardice. It means the spirit of manliness in
\n its perfection."[16]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Gandhi also follows the traditional Hindu belief that the life force with the
\n seminal fluid: A<\/span>All
\n power comes from the preservation and sublimation of the vitality that is
\n responsible for the creation of life. . . Perfectly controlled thought is
\n itself power of the highest potency and becomes self-acting. . . Such power is
\n impossible in one who dissipates his energy in any way whatsoever.@<\/span>[17]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a><\/div>\n\n\n The young Gandhi was very much attracted to the manly virtue of
\n the British and he was initially convinced of the widely held view that
\n meat-eating was essential for nourishing a man=<\/span>s
\n vital energies. His experiments with meat eating were a disaster and the
\n recovery of his Hindu heritage (thanks to the theosophists in London) and his
\n dramatic reconversion to vegetarianism were major turning points in his life.
\n As a result, a very different way of relating virtue to gender gradually arose
\n in his thinking. As he reflected back on his childhood, the power of
\n "self-suffering," modeled perfectly in his devout mother, moved to the center
\n of his struggle to find an acceptable philosophy of political engagement.
\n Transgressions in Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n home were dealt with by self-punishment, which became the model of Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n insistence on performing others=<\/span>
\n penance for them. <\/p>\n\n What the young Gandhi feared most at home was his father’s
\n self-suffering not his punishment, and the mature Gandhi had considerable
\n success in applying this insight against the British. As the Rudolphs have
\n shown, Gandhi discovered the connection between self-suffering and courage in
\n his South Africa campaigns. The virtues of patience, self-control, and
\n courage (we will later define these as
\n A<\/span>enabling@<\/span>)
\n were absolutely essential to defeat the temptation to retaliate and respond
\n with violence. Gandhi concluded that aggressive and retaliatory courage
\n demonstrated a complete lack of self-control; it actually shows impotence
\n rather than maniless. Satyagrahis must purge themselves of ill-will and their
\n goal must be the bring out the goodness in their opponents.<\/p>\n\n Let us now move to the crux of the issues of self-suffering,
\n courage, power, and nonviolence. Gandhi made it clear that each of these
\n virtues were found most often in women. The textual and experiential evidence
\n is quite persuasive: "Has she not great intuition, is she not more
\n self-sacrificing, has she not greater powers of endurance, has she not greater
\n courage?"[18]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n In 1936 he declared that ahimsa<\/i> is embodied in the woman: she is "weak
\n in striking. . . strong in suffering."[19]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n The women around Gandhi were amazed about how comfortable they felt in his
\n presence and how much of a woman he had become to them. (A<\/span>I
\n hope you have not missed the woman in me," he once said.)[20]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n His grandniece Manu considered Gandhi to be her new mother and simply could
\n not understand all the controversy surrounding their sleeping with one another.<\/div>\n\n\n Gandhi once said that he wanted to convert the woman=<\/span>s
\n capacity for A<\/span>self-sacrifice
\n and suffering into Shakti-power."[21]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n The Sanskrit shakti<\/i> is the power of the Hindu Goddess and, as opposed
\n to tejas<\/i>, is a necessary attribute that the Goddess shares with
\n everything in the universe. The Hindu Goddess theology essentially breaks the
\n vicious cycle of the Vedic maxim, explained superbly by Brian K. Smith,[22]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n that one gains power only at another’s expense. The Vedic power game, as with
\n most patriarchal concepts of power, is a zero-sum game. Those who control the
\n sacrifice, either by hook or by crook (with the gods dominating in the "crook"
\n department), control teja<\/i>s. The result is constant battles between
\n gods and antigods, gods and ascetics, priests and kings. Goddess theology is
\n radically different: shakti<\/i> is a power that all beings have by virtue
\n of their very existence. Ontologically speaking, tejas<\/i> is a quality
\n (seen most clearly in its meaning as fire as one of the primary elements of
\n the basic substance [bhuta<\/i>]) while shakti<\/i> is the basic
\n substance; or, more accurately, the basic process because Goddess philosophy
\n is clearly more compatible with process, rather than substance, metaphysics.<\/p>\n\n The Goddess scriptures were written by men and her sacred sites
\n were controlled by male priests, so it should not be surprising that she does
\n not always speak with a woman=<\/span>s
\n voice. In North India a husband must pay for fourteen recitations of the
\n Devi-Mahatmya<\/i>, the most famous Goddess scripture, in order to control an
\n unruly wife, but he only has to pay for twelve recitations to defeat an enemy.[23]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n A recitation of the same text may also protect a Hindu male’s genitals and
\n semen and help him get a good wife. Every year, at the beginning of the
\n warring season, Hindu kings sacrificed thousands of animals to the Goddess so
\n that their battles would go well. Mythologically, this translated into the
\n Goddess winning the great victories over the enemies of the Dharma with
\n incredible acts of violence and destruction.
\n At the 1999 Durga festival in
\n Calcutta, clay statues brave Indian soliders were added to the traditional
\n neighborhood altars to demonstrate how the Goddess made their victory in
\n Kargil possible.<\/span><\/div>\n\n\n Significantly, Gandhi embraces Goddess theology in a manner
\n more consistent than these traditional views. The most dramatic demonstration
\n of Shakti power was Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n pacification of the Pathan warriors, whom Kipling praised as the notable
\n exception to the cowardly effeminancy of the Indian people.
\n A<\/span>Brave they are as a
\n matter of course,@<\/span>
\n said Gandhi, A<\/span>[and]
\n to kill and get killed is an ordinary thing in their eyes, and if they are
\n angry with anyone, they will thrash him and sometimes even kill him.@<\/span>[24]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Ironically, the Pathan=<\/span>s
\n disposition to anger and uncontrolled retaliation describes the masculine
\n version of the Goddess=<\/span>s
\n action, while Gandhi unarmed moral courage in front of them is more consistent
\n with the shakti<\/i> view of shared power. Indeed, Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n Goddess does not decapitate nor does she impale; rather, she disarms and
\n attempts to reconcile warring peoples. Therefore, when Gandhi states that
\n "all power comes from the preservation and sublimation of the vitality that is
\n responsible for the creation of life@<\/span>[25]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n he must be referring to shakti<\/i> not tejas<\/i>.<\/p>\nVOWS AND
\n VIRTUES<\/b><\/div>\n\n\n Even though Gandhi does speak of the virtues and even
\n nonviolence as one, my attempt to make Gandhi a virtue ethicist is complicated
\n by the fact that Gandhi emphasized vows more than virtues. The fact that
\n a
\n person has to make a vow to discourage certain behavior clearly indicates that
\n this person is not naturally inclined to the virtuous action that counters the
\n vice. Even if this person is successful in her vow, she may still be virtuous
\n only, as I say, under duress–the pressures of temptation to lapse from the
\n vow. Gandhi believed that the greatest human failing is was weakness of the
\n will, and the taking of vows is the best cure for akrasia. In Aristotle=<\/span>s
\n terms the person who takes a vow is an akrates<\/i>, literally one without
\n the will overcome temptation. The enkrates<\/i> is one who has sufficient
\n will to resist but has not formed the habit of living naturally in the mean of
\n the virtue in question. Aristotle calls the latter a sophron<\/i>, one
\n who, as Confucius said of himself at the age of seventy:
\n A<\/span>I could give my
\n heart-mind free rein without overstepping the boundaries@<\/span>
\n (Analects<\/i> 2.4).<\/p>\n\n Let us illustrate this distinction with the following story.
\n Jack and Jill work as temporary tellers at a bank. The bank has only one
\n permanent teller position open, and either Jack or Jill will be chosen for the
\n job after a probationary period. As soon as he is on the job, Jack finds that
\n he has strong temptations to embezzle funds from this new employers. He finds
\n these temptations so troubling that he decides to take a solemn vow not to
\n follow through with these intentions. The vow works and Jack makes it through
\n the probationary without succumbing. Meanwhile at the other station, Jill goes
\n through her daily routine not once thinking of stealing funds.<\/p><\/div>\n\n\n Our story obviously makes Jack the enkrates<\/i> and Jill the
\n sophron. <\/i>(He would be an akrates<\/i> without the vow.) First, note
\n how absurd it would be for anyone to suggest that Jill needs to take the vow
\n that Jack has taken. Second, both Jack and Jill are deserving of praise, but
\n note that while we would commend Jill for her virtue, we can praise Jack only
\n for his will power to resist temptation. We may believe that Jack=<\/span>s
\n action has moral content, and some may even propose that Jack deserves higher
\n praise. (In fact, Immanuel Kant supports this view because we know for sure
\n that Jack is being honest out of duty and not just mere inclination, while
\n Jill=<\/span>s easy virtue
\n obscures her commitment to duty.) But I contend that more dramatic examples
\n of duress virtue–the person who has strong urges to murder every person that
\n she meets but always manages to restrain herself; or the man who wants to rape
\n every woman he meets but desistsB<\/span>demonstrates
\n that there may be no moral value to Jack=<\/span>s
\n heroic efforts. Third, let us say, just for the sake forcing the argument,
\n that the bank managers somehow learn of Jack=<\/span>s
\n temptations. (He frequently mutters to himself and pounds himself on the
\n forehead like Gandhi used to do.) It is clear that bank managers will
\n obviously not be able to trust Jack and that they will offer the job to Jill
\n without hesitation.<\/p>\n\n The point of the argument thus far is to suggest that an ethics
\n of virtues and a morality of vows are conceptually divergent and may also
\n assume significantly different views of human nature and the nature of evil.
\n It has been said that Aristotle did not fully appreciate the depth and extent
\n of human evil. While he can envision a person with insufficient will to
\n follow the mean, he cannot conceive of a person who deliberately wills evil and certainly not one who would
\n actually take pleasure in it. It is
\n significant that for Aristotle the only one
\n A<\/span>with will@<\/span>
\n (the literal meaning of enkrates<\/i>) is the person who stays in the mean
\n under duress not the person with the will to deliberately do evil. Aristotle
\n does admit that persistent misfortunate (Oedipus is a good example) can
\n destroy the conditions for personal happiness. The Stoics, however, read the
\n external world as one of insurmountable misery and the Christian view of
\n original sin further undermined the optimism and perfectionism of the
\n classical Greeks.<\/div>\n\n\n The Stoics=<\/span>
\n contribution to virtue ethics is considerable, but ironically they were
\n responsible for its eventual demise. As we have seen, the Stoics reaffirmed
\n the concept of virtues as skills and the fact that they are whole the entire
\n time they are expressed. However, their devaluation of the affective
\n dimensions of the human soul led to a position where virtue was an internal
\n process of conformation to cosmic reason and its laws. The Stoic withdrawal
\n from the world and from the body led to a rejection of the empirical ego in
\n favor of a universal self, one, as Epictetus said, who never sleeps, is never
\n deceived, and always knows the good. The Stoics then set the stage for the
\n full decline of virtue ethics in Christian philosophy. There is no good except
\n obedience to law, whether it be given by reason or God, whether it be by
\n divine command or out of the divine nature. Furthermore, the Stoic view that
\n success is not necessary for virtue leads, ironically, from Augustine to Kant,
\n to the view that the virtues are not necessary for morality at all. Only
\n Thomas Aquinas, under Aristotle=<\/span>s
\n profound influence, resisted this destruction of the classical virtue
\n tradition.<\/div>\n\n\n Augustine=<\/span>s
\n emphasis on original sin and the omnipotence of God led him to reject the
\n Greek view that we can develop the virtues on our own power. The dual
\n emphasis on sin and omnipotence also results in a paradoxical position on the
\n resolution of evil. For the Greeks, those who experience great misfortune had
\n no recourse except to endure it, and in Oedipus at Colonus<\/i> the hero,
\n comforted by his equally brave daughters, accepts his fate with grace and
\n equanimity. For the Christian, however, the extent and depth of evil is much
\n greater and punishment for sin is infinite torment. Some are surprised to
\n learn that even Kant believed in radical evil, the original sin against the
\n moral law that produces "infinite guilt." As Kant states: "It would seem to
\n follow, then, that because of this infinite guilt all mankind must look
\n forward to endless punishment and exclusion from the Kingdom of God."[26]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n On the bright side, the promise of God=<\/span>s
\n grace offers final and complete relief from all misfortune and suffering. For
\n the Greeks, the stakes are lower but complete reconciliation is impossible;
\n for the Christians the stakes are much higher but for the sincere person a
\n ready solution is right at hand. As Christine MacKinnon states:
\n A<\/span>The problem for the
\n agent who disobeys God is that the stakes are so high: the fate of his soul
\n must be the most important thing the agent is to consider when he contemplates
\n his welfare.@<\/span>[27]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>\n <\/p>\n\n\n Returning now to Gandhi, it appears that the taking of vows is
\n necessarily connected to rule ethics rather than virtue ethics. A vow can be
\n best seen as the self-enforcement of a rule. Gandhi is definitely more like
\n Kant than Aristotle if the Rudolphs are correct is saying that he held that
\n "only self-control in the midst of temptation was worthy."[28]<\/span><\/span><\/a>
\n Was Gandhi=<\/span>s view of
\n human nature so negative that he concluded that vows rather than the free
\n development of virtues was the only option for humankind? This, I submit, is
\n not Gandhi=<\/span>s view.
\n His neo-Vedantist view of the self and his negative views of the body and the
\n passions, however, align him very closely with the Stoics. As one of my
\n bright ethics students once said,
\n A<\/span>Duress virtue is the
\n father of natural virtue,@<\/span>
\n so we might think of Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n vows as instruments to train satyagrahis to develop the virtues necessary for
\n world peace. One could envision, especially within the context of Hindu
\n perfectionism, the Gandhian gradually moving from the enkrates<\/i> state to
\n that of the sophron. <\/i> Theoretically, however, the neo-Vedantist
\n position requires that we view the Atman as already morally perfect, so this
\n would be a "recovery" rather than a "developmental" view of the virtues. I
\n personally support the latter and that is why I propose the Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n ethics of nonviolence be reformulated along Pali Buddhist lines, for most
\n Mahayana Buddhist schools have reinstated the Higher Self of Vedanta.<\/p>\nGANDHI=<\/span>S
\n VOWS<\/b><\/div>\n\n\n Returning to the proposal that Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n vows could turn into virtues that people could enjoy, a critic might raise an
\n obvious objection. Why did the Mahatma himself never make this transition
\n and
\n why did he have to struggle with temptation all his life, even to the point of
\n frequently striking out against himself for his failings? His closest associates uniformly
\n attest to frequent outbursts of anger. Here is one of
\n Manu=<\/span>s observations:
\n A<\/span>While he was pouring
\n out his soul like this [objecting to good wool used as garlands], he looked
\n the very picture of a volcano in eruption.@<\/span>[29]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n This is not an image of Aristotle=<\/span>s
\n sophron<\/i>. Before 1906, when he took the first the vow of
\n brahmacharya<\/i>, he admitted that he was an akrates<\/i>, one who not only
\n lacked the will to deny himself the pleasures of sexual intercourse but also
\n one who had insufficient faith in the grace of God.[30]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n In 1939 he spoke of evil as a real force in the world and admitted that he had
\n much of it in him.[31]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Here is strong evidence that Gandhi cannot join Confucius, the Buddha, or
\n Aristotle in a humanistic developmental virtue ethics.
\n With their emphasis on evil and
\n divine grace, the passages above are strong support for a Christian rule and
\n duty ethics.<\/span><\/p>\n\n Gandhi believes that vows
\n A<\/span>can be taken only on
\n points of universally recognized principles,@<\/span>[32]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n and they are taken with the higher self as witness and the lower self and its
\n desires as the object of control. Typically, Gandhi moves from Vedantist
\n monism to personal theism with no hesitation. God is the perfect model of
\n inflexible resolve, because, as Gandhi explains,
\n A<\/span>God is the very image
\n of the vow. God would cease to be God if He swerved from His own laws even by
\n a hair=<\/span>s breadth.@<\/span>[33]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Gandhi, according to Suman Khanna, believed a vow to be a
\n A<\/span>sacred commitment to
\n God@<\/span> and that
\n A<\/span>breaking a vow is
\n tantamount to a breach of faith with God on the one hand, and being untruthful
\n to oneself on the other.@<\/span>[34]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Taking a vow is a way of grabbing hold of the Good=God and not letting it go.<\/p>\n<\/div>\n\n\n The Sanskrit word for vow is vrata<\/i> and its earliest use
\n in the Rigveda<\/i> is linked to divine will or command.[35]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n For Khanna a vow is an internal sanction: a
\n A<\/span>commitment to an
\n injunction voluntarily imposed one oneself.@<\/span>[36]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n For Gandhi a vow means having
\n A<\/span>unflinching determination [that] helps us against temptation,@<\/span>[37]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n so vow taking for him appears to be a form of duress virtue. It is a way of
\n storming the fortress of virtue and overcoming all odds and succeeding.
\n Presumably it is the only possible way to coerce yourself along the way of
\n moral perfection. Brahmacharya<\/i> does not become the effortless
\n disposition required by the sophron<\/i>; rather,
\n A<\/span>it is like walking on
\n the sword=<\/span>s edge, and
\n I see every moment the necessity for eternal vigilance.@<\/span>[38]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n (Here again is the Hindu dramatic vision of extremes rather than calm Buddhist
\n Middle Way.) While in South Africa he convinced himself that he could maintain
\n his vows with A<\/span>no
\n effort@<\/span> by simply
\n holding to his diet of fruit and nuts, although he did find that adding milk
\n made the vow difficult again. But these suggestions that humans on their own
\n power can consummate their vow are undermined by the strong assertion that
\n brahmacharya<\/i> is A<\/span>impossible
\n to attain by mere human effort.@<\/span>[39]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a><\/p>\n\n Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n language is ambiguous and not always consistent, so it is always difficult to
\n determine whether this is a Stoic-Kantian model or a traditional Christian
\n one, in which a transcendent God is directing the moral life. The Christian
\n view is seen in Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n strong hints that divine grace is necessary:
\n A<\/span>Win divine grace for
\n us in good time, and all artificial tastes will then disappear with the
\n realization of the Highest.@<\/span>[40]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n The Vedantist Gandhi would of course follow the Stoics and Kant, with Atman as
\n the immanent divinity giving itself (=gracing itself) the same cosmic laws
\n that others in tune with their higher selves would do. When we read that "the
\n straight way to cultivate brahamacharya is the Ramanama [repeating the name of
\n the god Rama]"; or that the initial vow of 1906 was successful only
\n A<\/span>with faith in the
\n sustaining power of God,@<\/span>[41]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n then the theistic perspective appears to dominate.<\/p>\n\n Before we analyze Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n principal vows, we should discuss the additional vows that Gandhi added,
\n consistent with his contextual pragmatism, for 20th<\/sup> Century India.
\n The addition of these vows can be seen as the direct result of Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n experiments in truth: they are, as he says,
\n A<\/span>directly deducible
\n from Truth.@<\/span>[42]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Furthermore, each them stands in considerable conflict with traditional Hindu
\n dharma<\/i>. The phrase
\n A<\/span>deducible
\n from Truth@<\/span> implies
\n logical deduction and a necessary relation between premisses and conclusions.
\n We have seen, however, that Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n experiments in truth is thoroughly empirical and, in addition, as
\n A<\/span>they are enjoined by
\n the present age,@<\/span> it
\n is clear that they are fully contingent. Indeed, if the socioeconomic
\n conditions that caused the need for these addition vows change, then the vows
\n would no longer be necessary. Therefore, we can establish a distinction
\n between basic and necessary vows, such as brahmacharya<\/i>, based as they
\n are on certain facts of human nature that will not change, and contingent vows
\n determined of the conditions of the
\n A<\/span>present age.@<\/span><\/div>\n\n\n First and foremost among the contingent vows is Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n demand that all Indians commit themselves to the elimination of untouchability.
\n Although many contemporary Indians still have great difficulty with this
\n imperative, the central government has implemented, not of course without
\n protest and controversial, a quota system for the scheduled castes, more
\n generally known today as the Dalits. The second vow of bread labor also
\n conflicts with traditional dharma<\/i> in that it requires all people
\n regardless of caste\/class to involve themselves in the dignity producing activity of physical labor. Indeed, Gandhi recommends that every person
\n commit herself\/himself regularly to the lowest menial labor as a gesture to
\n those who have done these jobs for centuries. (Gandhi himself went one step
\n further and prayed that he be reborn an untouchable.) The third vow of
\n sarvadharma samabh~<\/span>va
\n <\/i>extends the elimination of caste distinction to the tolerance of all
\n religious faiths. The conceptual similarity is deeper at the practical level:
\n Gandhi proposed that we not merely tolerate other religions but actually
\n attempt to step into their precepts and their forms of life. <\/p>\n\n The fourth and final vow for the present age is the vrata<\/i>
\n of swadeshi<\/i>, which is best translated as
\n A<\/span>self-realization@<\/span>
\n and is expressed personally and socially in a life of communal
\n self-sufficiency. In the context of Vedantist philosophy, self-realization is
\n the discovery of the Atman common to all people, so that the traditional
\n concept of autonomy is eliminated in the vow
\n A<\/span>of selfless service.
\n . . and the purest ahimsa<\/i>, i.e., love.@<\/span>[43]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Gandhi appears to equivocate on the contingent nature of swadeshi<\/i> when
\n he states that it A<\/span>stands
\n for the final emancipation of the soul from her earthly bondage.@<\/span>[44]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n This not only implies a necessary connection to human nature (thus making it a
\n basic vow), but the Vedantist overtones make this move highly problematic for
\n the social dimensions of swadeshi<\/i> and the fully embodied self that this
\n vow requires. \n<\/div>\n\n\n These fundamental problems are occasion to reaffirm a basic
\n thesis of this book: a Buddhist relational self is much better suited to
\n swadeshi<\/i> in that it prevents the loss of personal identity that all forms
\n of Vedanta imply (and that Advaita Vedanta asserts) and fully situates the
\n self in the body and society. For example, it is hard to understand how
\n A<\/span>cultivating
\n self-confidence@<\/span>[45]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n has any meaning if the individual self is ultimately unreal. This
\n self-confidence, Gandhi claims, is necessary for courage, a virtue that is
\n intelligible only on the basis of personal integrity and agency. To say that
\n Atman is fearless, when this entity has, strictly speaking, no qualities, is
\n to say nothing at all. Furthermore, a Buddhist interpretation would bring
\n Gandhi=<\/span>s ethics back
\n from the extremes that his vows tend to take him and encourages the
\n contemporary Gandhian to follow the Middle Way.<\/p>\n\n Returning to the basic vows, brahmacharya<\/i> is the supreme
\n vrata <\/i>that essentially includes all the others. It literally means
\n A<\/span>dwelling in Truth=God
\n [brahma<\/i>]<\/u>@<\/span>
\n and Nirmal Kumar Bose explains that it is
\n A<\/span>conduct that puts one
\n in touch with God.@<\/span>[46]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Generally taken to be a vow of chastity, Gandhi insists that it is much
\n broader than that: <\/p>\n\n [chastity] is impossible without proper control over all the
\n senses. They are all interdependent. Mind on the lower plane is included in
\n the senses. Without control over the mind, mere physical control, even if it
\n can be attained for a time, is of little or no use.[47]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a><\/p>\nControl of the
\n mind is obtained by taking the vow and initiating willful power over the
\n senses. The goal of brahmacharya<\/i> is nothing less than complete control
\n of A<\/span>thought, word,
\n and deed.@<\/span>[48]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n In his Autobiography<\/i> Gandhi claims that satyagraha<\/i> would not
\n have been possible without first succeeding in this supreme vow.<\/div>\n\n\n Gandhi offers a provocative connection between brahmacharya<\/i>
\n and nonviolence when he proposes that
\n A<\/span>lying naked with a
\n naked member of the opposite sex is the ultimate test for not doing violence
\n to another.@<\/span>[49]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n The axiom appears to be that if you can overcome the temptations of sex, then
\n you will also overcome the temptation to do violence and to retaliate. It is
\n also an expression of great courage, sufficient to withstand the criticism of
\n those who objected to such a risky experiment. When it comes to sexual
\n temptations, the isolated ascetic, according to Gandhi, does not fully trust
\n himself. He is actually a coward if he does put his self-control to the
\n ultimate test.<\/div>\n\n\n Interestingly enough, Gandhi adds control of the palate (asvada<\/i>)
\n to the traditional list of Hindu vows. Its literal meaning is not to eat
\n merely for the taste of food. Gandhi firmly believes that food should sustain
\n the body not please the palate. It is clear that this amounts to more than
\n Aristotle=<\/span>s mean
\n between gluttony and fasting. It also raises the issue about Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n own fasting and perhaps yet another difference between vows and virtues.
\n Vows, at least in Gandhian practice, tends to the extreme whereas classical
\n virtue theory sought the mean in all actions. Aristotle, Confucius, and the
\n Buddha would all agree that Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n fasts unto death would constitute a vice and not a virtue. (It is significant
\n that Aquinas also argued that fasting was a vice.)[50]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n One could contend that such fasts do in fact violate asvada<\/i> insofar as
\n its positive implication is that food is required for human nourishment.
\n Gandhi actually sounds very Aristotelian, even Buddhist, when he proposed that
\n we must always be mindful and adjust our food intake according to our own
\n bodily needs.[51]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n (In terms of our discussion of experiments in truth, we could say that to eat
\n more than we need is to be untruthfulB<\/span>in
\n the strict factual sense that our bodies do not need the extra calories.) The
\n body must therefore be kept fit for spiritual service. This positive
\n imperative of asvada<\/i> is therefore at odds with a political fast unto
\n death in which the constant worry of course was Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n health.<\/p>\n\n With regard to the vows of asteya <\/i>(nonstealing) and nonpossesion (aparigraha<\/i>) Gandhi proposed
\n an experiment in truth that
\n tested the full implications of these vows. (The meaning of truth most appropriate for these two vows is the Greek sense of nonconcealment [aletheia<\/i>]).
\n Gandhi=<\/span>s special way
\n to test his own and any possible thief=<\/span>s
\n commitment to asteya<\/i> was to leave all possessions in the full light of
\n day. (In his controversial tests of brahmacharya<\/i> he also insisted on
\n open sleeping arrangements to demonstrate that his bed partners were not his
\n sexual possessions. (This seems to imply that the veiling of women is a major
\n violation of asteya<\/i>.) Not concealing your possessions means that you
\n confuse potential thieves in a way that can best help them overcome their
\n temptations. They would also be morally disarmed by your lack of concern for
\n your possessions and could very well serve as a way of shaming them to realize
\n their own extreme possessiveness. In fact, it seems to be a rule that the
\n more people possess the more they are forced to conceal and to secureB<\/span>sometimes
\n a great cost and inconvenience to themselves. Gandhi believes that to look
\n with envy at the possessions of another is to violate asetya<\/i>, and even
\n the one who fasts sins if he casts a desirous eye at any food.[52]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Gandhi makes the vow of nonpossession so comprehensive that he concludes that
\n A<\/span>everyone of us is
\n consciously or unconsciously more or less guilty of theft.@<\/span>[53]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Again Gandhi=<\/span>s ethics
\n of vows tends to the extreme rather than the mean. Even the most accomplished
\n (=spiritual) fasters hallunicate about food, so Gandhi appears to be in strict
\n agreement with the Yoga-sutras<\/i> which requires that one not only control
\n all conscious desires but also unconscious ones as well.<\/div>\n\n\n The fifth and final vow is fearlessness (abhaya<\/i>) and the
\n fact that this vrata<\/i> is related to the virtue of courage allows us to
\n make a transition from vows to virtues; or to anticipate our goal more
\n precisely–to reinterpret the vows as enabling virtues later in this chapter.
\n Except for brahmacharya<\/i>, each of the vows is expressed with the
\n Indo-European A<\/span>a@<\/span>
\n privative: no stealing, no possession, and no fear. This form of expression
\n intensifies the notion of extremes in Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n ethics of vows. For Aristotle, having no fear could be foolhardy and
\n dangerous and would not always be what right reason (phronesis<\/i>)
\n requires. Suman Khanna, however, argues that Gandhi believes that the virtue
\n (not vow) of humility is a precondition for all the vows. Proper humility
\n prevents foolhardiness because the humble person does not overestimate
\n A<\/span>one=<\/span>s
\n resources of courage.@<\/span>[54]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n We shall follow Khanna=<\/span>s
\n constructive proposal in the next section where will discuss Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n virtues. Before we do so, there is one issue that requires attention. Gandhi
\n claims that abhaya<\/i> A<\/span>connotes
\n freedom from all external fear@<\/span>[55]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n and the key to this freedom is to distinguish between our true spiritual
\n natures and our bodies. The reader should not be surprised that I encourage
\n contemporary Gandhians to reject this advise and embrace a fully embodied self
\n that an ethics of nonviolence and political engagement requires.<\/p>\nGANDHI=<\/span>S
\n VIRTUES<\/b><\/p>\n\n\n I have felt during the whole of my public life that what we
\n need, what any nation needs, but we perhaps of all the nations of the world
\n need just now, is nothing else and nothing less than character building.<\/p>\n\n First of all, we shall have to consider how we can realise the
\n self and how serve our country . . . . For realising the self, the first
\n essential thing is to cultivate a strong moral sense. Morality means
\n acquisition of virtues such as fearlessness, truth, chastity, etc. Service is
\n automatically rendered to the country in this process of cultivating morality.[56]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>\n <\/p>\n\n A Buddhist Gandhi would follow the developmental model of
\n virtue formation found in Aristotle and Confucius. The recovery model–found
\n in Plato, the Stoics, a few neo-Confucians, some Mahayana schools, and VedantaB<\/span>holds
\n that moral education involves coming in touch with a higher self that its already perfect. In terms of
\n a Hindu ethics of nonviolence this would mean
\n that one acts out the Atman of perfect virtue rather than a self-centered
\n jiva<\/i>. In this model a vow is a life long requirement to keep the violent
\n ego in control. Only in the perfected yogi would the vows fall away as
\n unnecessary. Suman Khanna suggests the developmental model for Gandhi when she
\n states that the commitment of a vow
\n A<\/span>becomes effortless,
\n just as the forming of good habits first needs continual effort of the will
\n but later grows into character, from which good choices issue forth with ease.@<\/span>[57]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a><\/p>\n<\/div>\n\n\n If we analyze the list of Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n vows and virtues, we notice at least two interesting points. First, Gandhi
\n considers chastity both a vow and a virtue, and in his detailed comments on
\n Hind Swaraj<\/i> Anthony Parel calls the vow of nonpossession a virtue.[58]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n If these are virtues in the traditional sense of a disposition that becomes
\n habitual rather than constantly self-imposed, then the developmental thesis is
\n supported. Second, humility is a virtue not a vow, and Gandhi is very careful
\n to distinguish between the two categories with regard to humility. Gandhi
\n maintains that one cannot take a vow to become humble. Humility does not
\n involve a specific decision or course of action. As he states:
\n A<\/span>Humility . . . does
\n not lend itself to being deliberately practised.@<\/span>[59]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Objections immediately arise. Is not reducing ourselves to zero a specific
\n decision and action? Doesn=<\/span>t
\n Gandhi contradict himself when he states that
\n A<\/span>true humility means
\n most strenuous and constant endeavor entirely directed towards the service of
\n humanity@<\/span>?[60]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n We will return to the virtue of humility at the end of this section.<\/p>\n\n Gandhi joins the ancient virtue traditions by strongly
\n supporting the unity of the virtues. To interpret this doctrine as the claim
\n that the virtues have no differences whatsoever is of course absurd. For the
\n Greeks the virtues were one in the sense that virtue is knowledge. Each of
\n them is formed according to right reason. For Aristotle the moral virtues are
\n the same because they are products of phronesis<\/i>, and they are different
\n because of the many different spheres of action in which phronesis<\/i>
\n works. Phronesis<\/i> operating in the sphere of self-worth becomes pride,
\n just as temperance is the result in the area of controlling the appetites. I
\n propose that Gandhi follows Aristotle by having truth unify the virtues.
\n Following Jean Porter=<\/span>s
\n analysis of Aquinas, I also concur with her emphasis on the dialectical
\n relation between phronesis<\/i> and the virtues: the former not only finds
\n the mean for the latter but the development of the moral virtues aids
\n practical reason in clarifying and fine tuning the goals of the good life.[61]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n The moral virtues embody truths just as much as practical reason itself does.<\/div>\n\n\n Alan Donagan=<\/span>s
\n maintains that unifying the virtues in phronesis<\/i> produces only a
\n trivial truth: A<\/span>Certainly
\n Thomas=<\/span> doctrine of
\n the unity of the virtues follows if every virtue is defined as a disposition
\n that accords with right reason. But why so define themB<\/span>except
\n to secure the result?@<\/span>[62]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n It seems to me, however, that as right reason is always relative to
\n individuals and their circumstances, then their moral truths are synthetic
\n rather than analytic. These propositions would obviously have specific
\n empirical content as well as formal truth. (This makes
\n A<\/span>Never eat too much@<\/span>
\n a synthetic a priori<\/i> proposition, because the formal truth is
\n necessarily joined with unique and distinctive empirical content in every
\n single eater.) If the mean between extremes were arithmetic and the same for all persons,
\n a view that Aristotle explicitly rejects,[63]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n only then would the results of practical reason be trivially true.<\/p>\n\n In chapter 4 we have argued that Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n experiments in truth is a contextual and pragmatic search for particular moral
\n truths for particular situations. This means that the traditional truths
\n about brahmacharya <\/i>are deconstructed and then reapplied in a
\n constructive postmodern sense. Writing from the Yeravda prison in 1932, he
\n states that A<\/span>truth is
\n the end, love is the means thereto.@<\/span>[64]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n For Gandhi true love is the A<\/span>active
\n state of ahimsa,@<\/span>[65]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n and courage is following one=<\/span>s
\n own truth even to the point of ridicule and rejection. The virtues of
\n integrity and sincerity, being true to oneself, are also necessary virtues in
\n the search for truth. We have already proposed a parallel between the
\n relationship of truth to God in Gandhi to the Confucian idea of Heaven=<\/span>s
\n sincerity. The sage or saint are sincere in the same way that Heaven is: they
\n are both constant and totally predictable; they are both true themselves and
\n true to the present age.<\/div>\n\n\n It is significant that Gandhi speaks much more of self-control
\n than temperance; in fact, the latter is seldom found in his writings. In talk
\n about the virtues the two are often conflated, when in fact they are distinct
\n in a very important sense. The very construction of the phrase
\n A<\/span>self-control@<\/span>
\n implies that one is engaging the will to restrain the appetites. This
\n describes the enkrates<\/i> rather than sophron<\/i>, who is essentially
\n the embodiment of temperance (sophrosyne<\/i>), the one who does not have to
\n exert his will to stay in the mean. Gandhi thought that one the greatest
\n Indian vices was the lack of self-control. The Rudolphs diagnose the origins
\n of this problem: "The severe emphasis on self-restraint [in the Indian
\n tradition], on formality and harmlessness, may well be allied to the
\n omnipresent fear of loss of self-control."[66]<\/span><\/span><\/a>
\n This emphasis on self-control rather than temperance indicates an ethics of
\n vows and duties rather than virtues.<\/p>\n\n Raghavan Iyer offers an alternative framework for the Gandhian
\n virtues in his observation that "Gandhi tended to assimilate all the virtues
\n to that of moral courage."[67]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Even in his time Aristotle had realized that courage was more than just the
\n physical bravery of his Greek forefathers, who
\n A<\/span>strutted their stuff@<\/span>
\n with drawn swords. Susanne and Lloyd Rudolph distinguish between physical
\n bravery–not being afraid to use violence to defend one=<\/span>s
\n home and principles–and Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n nonviolent moral courage as the will not to retaliate in the face of violence.
\n
\n
\n [68]<\/span><\/a><\/span> Recall
\n that Confucius warned his disciples that many people could be brave without
\n being ren<\/i>, the obvious implication being that truly courageous people
\n know and trust themselves so well that the force of their virtue (the Chinese
\n de <\/i>expresses this idea perfectly) tends to pacify any dangerous
\n situation. We have seen that Gandhi was able to convinced the physically
\n brave Pathan warriors to change their ways by his moral courage. In terms of
\n the aesthetics of virtue and the power of de <\/i>it is significant that
\n Confucius and his disciples were able to fend off an attack simply by singing.\n <\/p>\n\n\n In its positive form, ahimsa means the largest love, the
\n greatest charity. If I am a follower of ahimsa, I must love my enemy. I must
\n apply the same rule of the wrong doer who is my enemy or a stranger to me, as
\n I would to my wrong-doing father or son. This active ahimsa necessarily
\n includes truth and fearlessness.[69]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a> \n <\/p>\n\n Instructive comparisons suggest themselves from both Confucius
\n and Aquinas. For the former ren<\/i> as filial love is the comprehensive
\n virtue that authenticates all the other virtues. Ideally the ren<\/i>
\n person would not and could not dissemble in any of the virtues; it would be
\n impossible for the ren <\/i>person not to be loyal or courageous or not to
\n be true to herself. A principal difference between Gandhi and Confucius would
\n be the unconditional love of the stranger, a view that obviously makes him
\n closer to the Buddhist or Christian tradition. For Aquinas caritas<\/i> is
\n ultimate form of all the virtues, including prudence; it, like ren<\/i>, is
\n the comprehensive virtue in which all the others are perfected. Thomist Josef
\n Pieper distinguishes between
\n A<\/span>natural@<\/span> and
\n A<\/span>Christian@<\/span>
\n prudence such that the latter is a keener insight into
\n A<\/span>new and invisible
\n realities.@<\/span>[70]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n Both Aristotle and Confucius would balk at this supernatural extension of
\n practical reason, but Gandhi would most likely embrace the idea. (Even the
\n Buddha would say that ESP was crucial in proving the truth of
\n A<\/span>those who know
\n causality know the Dharma.@<\/span>)
\n Gandhi would have been particularly sympathetic to Pieper=<\/span>s
\n view that Christian love may very well lead one to hold
\n A<\/span>as nought all the
\n things of this world.@<\/span>[71]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a><\/div>\n\n\n Gandhi says that people can cultivate truth and love, but they
\n try to make themselves humble only at the risk of hypocrisy and pride. The
\n reason for this odd stance might be the Vedantist assumptions implied in this
\n passage: A<\/span>In one who
\n has ahimsa in him [humility] becomes part of his very nature.@<\/span>[72]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n In several passage Gandhi that the true self is nonviolent, so this means that
\n the true self is also humble. (The concept of the self being nonviolent by
\n nature will be critiqued in the next section.) This is not quite correct
\n because true humility A<\/span>should
\n make its possessor realize that he is nothing.@<\/span>[73]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n But Atman is not nothing; it is of course everything. It can only be the
\n jiva<\/i> self that is reduced to nothing. Coherence is finally obtained when
\n Gandhi describes the humble self as analogous to a drop in the ocean as
\n jiva<\/i> is to Atman=Brahman. On the virtue of humility it is obvious that
\n Gandhi again joins the Christian tradition and rejects Aristotle=<\/span>s
\n view that humility is a vice. For the Greeks
\n A<\/span>reducing oneself to
\n zero@<\/span> could never be
\n the correct view of one=<\/span>s
\n self-worth. <\/p>\nNONVIOLENCE
\n AS AN ENABLING VIRTUE<\/b><\/p>\n\n Virtue theorists have generally distinguished between two types
\n of virtues: "enabling" virtues and the "substantive" virtues. The enabling
\n virtues include optimism, rationality, self-control, patience, sympathy,
\n foresight, resoluteness, endurance, fortitude, and industry. The substantive
\n virtues are wisdom, courage, justice, truthfulness, temperance, benevolence, and compassion. The substantive virtues have moral content or "substance,"
\n i.e., the right desire to tell the truth or help the needy, whereas the
\n enabling virtues simply require an effort to resist one temptation or another. The substantive virtues require proper motivation toward the good,
\n while the enabling virtues require sufficient willpower to counter evil. Of
\n the four cardinal virtues, only prudence and justice
\n A<\/span>do the good,@<\/span>
\n as Josef Pieper says, while courage and temperance
\n A<\/span>create the basis this
\n realization of the good.@<\/span>[74]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a><\/div>\n\n\n This distinction tests true when he think of a thief who is
\n persistent, resolute, patient, and has fantastic self-control. (Thieves
\n without these virtues are usually that ones that get caught!) The fact that
\n we can think of a loyal and courageous villain has led some to argue
\n convincingly that these two virtues really ought to be moved to the enabling
\n category. Another psychological test by which one can distinguish the two is
\n to use Aristotle’s requirement that one must take pleasure in the virtues.
\n This criterion must apply only to the substantive virtues, because it is clear
\n that one is not required to enjoy a courageous act of persevering torture.
\n As
\n Robert C. Roberts quips: "A person who enjoys enduring dangers is better
\n called daredevilish than brave."[75]<\/span><\/sup><\/sup><\/span><\/a>
\n On the other hand, it makes no sense that a person must dislike being truthful
\n or compassionate. This means that a person could have all the enabling
\n virtues without having a single substantive virtue.<\/div>\n\n\n Let us now itemize the criteria for identifying an enabling
\n virtue: (1) it does not have moral content nor does it appeal to a norm; (2)
\n it is not done for its own sake, but for the sake of a substantive virtue; and
\n (3) one does not take pleasure in it as with the substantive virtues.
\n Conceived as a virtue, nonviolence fulfills these criteria nicely. We all
\n need a nonviolent disposition if we are to overcome desires to injure,
\n retaliate, and to verbally abuse. We also need good self control and
\n patience. In fact, Gandhi equates impatience with injury (himsa<\/i>),
\n provocatively implying that impatience is at the root of all violence.76<\/span><\/a>
\n (One could object that much violence in the world is done with deliberate,
\n albeit malicious, patience.) Self control, patience, and noninjury are
\n obviously connected to the will to resist rather than the will to motivate.
\n (Recall the Rudolph=<\/span>s
\n definition of Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n nonviolent moral courage as the will not to retaliate in the face of
\n violence.) That means that a nonviolent thief is not only possible but also
\n probably the most successful. It is also clear that one does not control
\n oneself for the sake of self-control, nor is one nonviolent simply for the
\n sake of noninjury. Furthermore, resisting the temptation of retaliation while
\n enduring the attacks of an aggressor would obviously not be a pleasant
\n activity. Finally, it appears reasonable to reinterpret Gandhi=<\/span>s
\n basic vows as enabling virtues with brahmacharya<\/i> embracing them all as
\n ultimate self-control.<\/p>\n\n Our discovery that ahimsa<\/i> is an enabling virtue explains
\n why it is not listed among the major Buddhist virtues. Ahimsa<\/i> ,
\n therefore, joins patience, sympathy, and self-control, three other enabling
\n virtues in Buddhist ethics. The Dalai Lama=<\/span>s
\n analysis of the virtues parallels the current discussion in a way that allows
\n a conceptual transition to the final section of our chapter. When he
\n reaffirms that the cessation of suffering is the ultimate goal of the good
\n life, he is simply giving the negative formulation of the Buddhist eudaimonism
\n defended in chapter 4. When he states that faith and compassion are
\n A<\/span>virtues by way of
\n their own nature,@<\/span> he
\n is essentially identifying them as substantives virtues. And when he
\n describes mindfulness is a virtue
\n A<\/span>by way of association,@<\/span> I
\n interpret this to mean that it is an enabling virtue.77<\/span><\/a>
\n One is not mindful for mindfulness sake but for the sake of love and
\n compassion.\n<\/div>\n\n\n Let us return to Jainism for an instructive contrast. The
\n Jains believe that ahimsa<\/i> belongs to "the intrinsic nature of man,"78<\/span><\/a>
\n and they hold that it has absolute value. The implication is that
\n nonviolence is a A<\/span>substantive@<\/span>
\n virtue in a stronger, metaphysical sense than we have defined it above. Jain
\n nonviolence is not anything motivated or developed, it is simply the natural
\n state of the sinless soul. (This means that the Jains have a
\n A<\/span>recovery@<\/span>
\n rather than a A<\/span>discovery@<\/span>
\n model for the virtues.) In several passages Gandhi appears to agree with Jains
\n on this point, particularly when he states that atman<\/i> is nonviolent.
\n More frequently, however, he says that ahimsa <\/i>is a virtue that must be
\n attained, and he claims that it is a means to a higher end, usually Truth or
\n God.86<\/span><\/a>
\n Resisting the natural temptation to absolutize it, Gandhi has ascer\ufffdtained the
\n proper place of ahimsa<\/i> among the virtues. Ahimsa<\/i> begins in
\n self-restraint, self-purifi\ufffdcation, and selfless\ufffdness and ends in love and
\n compassion. Like the Buddhists, Gandhi believed that ahimsa<\/i> without
\n compas\ufffdsion is nothing, just as gold is an amorphous material without
\n gold\ufffdsmith’s artistic shape or the root is nothing without the mag\ufffdnificent
\n tree.
\n 79<\/a><\/span> The enabling virtues are the roots, but the flowering tree of the substantive virtues is the true
\n goal of the good life.<\/p>\n
\n Making ahimsa<\/i> a disposition rather than the essence of the soul
\n preser\ufffdves the essential element of freedom. Gandhi frequently spoke of the
\n animal side of human nature, and how one must struggle to choose violence over
\n non\ufffdviolence. (As in all enabling virtues, it involves the will to resist
\n more than the will to motivate.) If we are nonviolent by nature, then we
\n cannot be praised for choosing peaceful actions. On the other hand, we cannot
\n be completely devoid of a disposition for noninjury, for, as Gandhi says,
\n "means to be means must always be within our reach."80<\/span><\/a>
\n (One is reminded of the Mencian view that the virtues exist as potentials
\n within the soul; and, like spouts, they must be nurtured for the good life to
\n flower.) The language of
\n A<\/span>means
\n within our reach@<\/span> is
\n support for the developmental view of the virtues that we should impute to
\n Gandhi. Further\ufffdmore, Gandhi frequently reminds us that true ahimsa<\/i>
\n towards an attacker must combine physical non\ufffdretaliation with love and
\n compassion. (In other words, mere passivity without the proper disposition
\n and accompanying virtues is not necessarily ahimsa<\/i>.) Therefore,
\n ahimsa<\/i> must be a means to the end of the spiritual life, not an end in
\n itself. The true proponent of non\ufffdviolence would hold that only life (Gandhi
\n prefers Truth or God) has intrinsic value, and ahimsa<\/i> obviously is the ultimate means of preserving life. \n<\/div>\nENDNOTES<\/h1>\n
\n
\n <\/p>\n
<\/p>\n\n\n 1.
\n Quoted in Raghavan Iyer, The Moral the Political Thought of Mahatma
\n Gandhi<\/i> (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1973), p. 226; Gandhi,
\n Collected Works <\/i>(New Delhi: Govern\ufffdment of India Publications, 1959),
\n vol. 40, p. 160.\n <\/div>\n\n2. Wendy Doniger O=<\/span>Flaherty,
\n Asceticism and Eroticism in the Mythology of Shiva<\/i> (Oxford: Oxford
\n University Press, 1973), p. 82.<\/div>\n\n3. See Ian Tattersall,
\n The Last Neanderthal<\/i> (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, revised ed.,
\n 1999), p. 169-70.<\/div>\n\n4. Michael L. Spangle and Kent E. Menzel,
\n A<\/span>Symbol, Metaphor,
\n and Myth: the Origin and Impact of Spoken Language,@<\/span>
\n Seventh Annual Meeting of the Language Origins in DeKalb, Illinois, 1991;
\n http:\/\/baserv.uci.kun.nl\/~los\/Meetings\/Dekalb\/Articles\/ 24‑MENZEL.htm. It is
\n well known, for example, that deaf school children who read without speaking
\n a language have difficulty in understanding abstractions (see Helmer R.
\n Mykelbust, The Psychology of Deafness<\/i> [New York: Northwestern
\n University Press, 1966]). I am indebted to Shane Sheffner, student in my
\n seminar on virtue ethics, for these references.<\/p>\n<\/p><\/div>\n
\n5. Leslie Stephen,
\n The Science of Ethics<\/i>, quoted in Louis P. Pojman, Ethics: Discovering
\n Right and Wrong<\/i> (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1990), p. 114.
\n The following four part critique of rule and duty ethics is derived from Pojman=<\/span>s chapter.<\/div>\n\n6. Martha Nussbaum,
\n A<\/span>Non-Relative
\n Virtues@<\/span> in
\n Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Vol. 13<\/i> (Notre Dame, IN: Dotre Dame
\n University Press, 1988), p. 44.<\/div>\n\n7. Annette Baier,
\n A<\/span>Trust and
\n Anti-Trust,@<\/span>
\n Ethics<\/i> 96 (January, 1986), pp. 231-260.<\/div>\n\n8. Martha Nussbaum,
\n A<\/span>Non-Relative
\n Virtues,@<\/span> p. 44. <\/p><\/div>\n\n9. Bernard Mayo,
\n Ethics and the Moral Life<\/i>, excerpted in Christina and Fred Sommers,
\n eds., Vice and Virtue in Everyday Life<\/i> (San Diego: Harcourt Brace
\n Jovanovich, 1989), p. 199.<\/div>\n\n\n 10.
\n Ibid., p. 83.<\/p><\/div>\n\n\n 11.
\n Ibid., p. 84.<\/p><\/div>\n\n12. See Stephen D. Moore
\n and Janice Capel Anderson,
\n A<\/span>Taking it Like a Man: Masculinity in 4 Maccabees,@<\/span>
\n Journal of Biblical Literature<\/i> 117:2 (1998), pp. 249-273.<\/div>\n\n13. The Laws of Manu<\/i>,
\n trans. Wendy Doniger O=<\/span>Flaherty
\n and Brian K. Smith (New Delhi: Penguin Books, 1991), 3.93; 7.5. Most of this
\n paragraph is taken from my Spiritual Titanism: Indian, Chinese, and
\n Western Perspectives <\/i>(Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 2000), p. 122.<\/div>\n\n14. Ibid., 4:41, 44.<\/p><\/div>\n
\n15. John Strachey,
\n India: Its Adminstration and Progress<\/i> (London: Macmillan, 1888), p. 412;
\n cited in Susanne H. and Lloyd I. Rudolph, The Modernity of Tradition:
\n Political Development in India<\/i> (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago
\n Press, 1967), p. 165.<\/div>\n\n16. Gandhi, The
\n Collected Works<\/i>, vol. 19, p. 12.<\/div>\n\n17. Gandhi, Harijan<\/i>
\n (July 23, 1938), p. 192.<\/div>\n\n18. Gandhi, Women’s
\n Role in Society<\/i>, p. 8; cited in Iyer, Moral and Political Philosophy,
\n p. 37<\/i>.<\/div>\n\n19. Gandhi, Harijan<\/i>
\n (November 14, 1936), p. 316. "Woman is the incarnation of ahimsa<\/i>.
\n Ahimsa<\/i> means infinite love, which again means infinite capacity for
\n suffering" (Harijan<\/i> [February 14, 1940] ).
\n A<\/span>If only the women
\n of the world would come together they could display such heroic nonviolence
\n as to kick away the atom bomb like a mere ball. . . . If the women of Asia
\n wake up, they will dazzle the world. My experiment in nonviolence would be
\n instantly successful if I could secure women=<\/span>s
\n help@<\/span> (A<\/span>Message
\n to Chinese Women, New Delhi, July 18, 1947, excerpted in Raghavan Iyer, ed.,
\n The Essential Writings of Mahatma Gandhi<\/i> [New Delhi: Oxford
\n University Press, 1991, p. 387).<\/div>\n\n20. Pyarelal, The Last
\n Phase<\/i>, vol. 1, p. 595. Pyarelal states that Gandhi once described
\n himself as A<\/span>half a
\n woman,@<\/span> and Mrs. Polak
\n noted a A<\/span>trait
\n of sexlessness@<\/span> even
\n in his South Africa day (Gandiji as We Know Him<\/i>, ed. Ch. Shukla
\n [Bombay, 1945], p. 47). A Mrs. Shukla said that
\n A<\/span>there are some
\n things relating to our lives that we women can speak of . . . with no man.
\n But while speaking to Gandhiji we somehow forgot the fact that he was a man@<\/span>
\n (C. Shukla, Gandhiji=<\/span>s
\n View of Life<\/i> [Bombay, 1951], p. 199).<\/div>\n\n21.
\n <\/span>Pyarelal, The Last Phase<\/i>, vol. 1, p. 574.<\/div>\n\n22. Brian K. Smith,
\n "Eaters, Food, and Social Hierarchy in Ancient India," Journal of the
\n American Academy of Religion<\/i> 58:2 (Summer, 1990), pp. 177, 178. <\/p><\/div>\n\n\n 23. <\/span>Thomas B. Coburn,
\n Encountering the Goddess<\/i> (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 1991), p. 222fn.<\/p>\n<\/span>\n <\/div>\n
\n24. Gandhi, Selected
\n Works<\/i>, ed. Shriman Narayan (Ahmedabad: Navajivan, 1968), vol. 3, p. 223.<\/div>\n\n25. Gandhi, Harijan<\/i>
\n (July 23, 1938), p. 192. \n <\/div>\n\n26. Kant, Religion
\n within the Limits of Religion Alone<\/i>, trans. Theodore M. Greene and Hoyt
\n H. Hudson (New York: Harper & Row, 1960). p. 66.<\/div>\n\n27. Christine McKinnon,
\n Character, Virtue Theories, and the Vices<\/i> (Peterborough, Ontario:
\n Broadview Press, 1999), p. 105.<\/div>\n\n28. The Rudolphs,
\n op. cit., p. 212.<\/p>\n<\/p><\/div>\n
\n29. Pyarelal, Mahatma
\n Gandhi: The Last Phase<\/i> (Ahmedabad: Navajivan, 2nd<\/sup> ed., 1966),
\n vol. 1, bk. 2, p. 192.<\/div>\n\n30. Gandhi,
\n Autobiography<\/i> III.7.<\/div>\n\n31. Gandhi, Harijan<\/i>
\n (June 10, 1939).<\/div>\n\n32. Gandhi, Selected
\n Works<\/i>, vol. 4, p. 248.<\/div>\n\n33. Ibid., p. 250.<\/p><\/div>\n
\n34. Suman Khanna,
\n Gandhi and the Good Life<\/i> (Delhi: B. R. Publishing Corporation, 2nd<\/sup>
\n ed., 1996), p. 60. I am indebted to Khanna for both insights and
\n references.<\/div>\n\n35. See V. M. Bedekar,
\n A<\/span>The Vrata in
\n Ancient Indian Culture and Gandhi@<\/span>
\n in G. Ramachandran and T. K. Mahadevan, eds. Quest for Gandhi<\/i> (New
\n Delhi: Gandhi Peace Foundation, 1970), p. 15.<\/div>\n\n36. Khanna, p. 59.<\/p><\/div>\n
\n37. Gandhi, Selected
\n Works,<\/i> vol. 4, p. 248.<\/div>\n\n38. Gandhi,
\n Autobiography<\/i>, III.8.<\/div>\n\n39. Gandhi, Selected
\n <\/i>Works, vol. 4, p. 248.<\/div>\n\n40. Ibid., p. 226.<\/p><\/div>\n
\n41. Gandhi, Harijan<\/i>
\n (June 22 & 29, 1947), pp. 200, 212; Autobiography<\/i> III.7.<\/p><\/div>\n\n42.
\n <\/span>Quoted without reference in Khanna, p. 75.<\/div>\n\n43. Gandhi, Selected
\n Works<\/i>, vol. 4, p. 256.<\/div>\n\n44. Ibid.<\/p><\/div>\n
\n45. Ibid., p. 233.<\/p><\/div>\n
\n46. Gandhi, Selections
\n from Gandhi<\/i>, ed,. Nirmal Kumar Bose (Ahmedabad: Navajivan Publishing, 2nd<\/sup>
\n ed., 1957), p. 248.<\/div>\n\n47. Ibid., p. 249.<\/p><\/div>\n
\n48. Ibid.<\/p><\/div>\n
\n49. Pyarelal, The Last Phase<\/i>, vol. 1, p. 591; Letter to Rajkumari
\n Amrit Kaur, March 18, 1947.<\/div>\n\n50. Thomas
\n Aquinas,
\n Summa Theologiae<\/i> II-II.147.1ad2.<\/div>\n\n51. Gandhi, Selected
\n Works<\/i>, vol. 4, p. 226.<\/div>\n\n52.
\n A<\/span>One who takes no
\n food, physically speaking, is generally said to be fasting, but he is guilty
\n of theft as well as a breach of his fast, if he gives himself up to a mental
\n contemplation of pleasure, when he sees others taking their meals@<\/span>
\n (ibid., p. 228). It is a widely known fact that even the spiritual masters
\n have vivid hallucinations about devouring great amounts of food, a reaction
\n that appears to be completely involuntary.\n <\/div>\n\n53. Ibid., p. 227.<\/p><\/div>\n
\n54. Khanna, p. 71.<\/p><\/div>\n
\n55. Gandhi, Selected
\n Works<\/i>, vol. 4, p. 232.<\/div>\n\n56. Gandhi, Collected
\n Works<\/i>, vol. 37, p. 362; vol. 13, p. 225.; vol.10, p. 70. See also
\n vol.10, pp. 206-07.<\/div>\n\n57. Khanna, pp. 59-60.<\/p><\/div>\n
\n58. Gandhi, Hind
\n Swaraj<\/i>, ed. Anthony J. Parel (New Delhi, Foundation Books, 1997), note
\n 193.<\/div>\n\n59. Gandhi, Selected
\n Works<\/i>, vol. 4, p.245.<\/div>\n\n60. Ibid., p. 247.<\/p><\/div>\n
\n61.<\/span>
\n Jean Porter, "<\/span>Virtue and Sin:
\n The Connection of the Virtues and the Case of the Flawed Saint,"Journal
\n of Religion <\/i>75:4 (October, 1995), pp. 526-27.
\n <\/i>\n <\/div>\n\n\n
\n
\n [62]<\/span><\/span><\/a>.
\n Cited in ibid., p. 522.<\/i><\/div>\n\n\n
\n
\n [63]<\/span><\/span><\/a>.
\n Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics<\/i> 1106a35.<\/span><\/div>\n\n64. Gandhi, Selected
\n Works<\/i>, vol. 4, p. 226.<\/div>\n\n65. Gandhi,
\n Young India<\/i> (January 19, 1921).<\/div>\n\n66. The Rudolphs,
\n op. cit., p. 190.<\/p>\n<\/p><\/div>\n
\n\n 67.
\n Raghavan Iyer, The Moral and Political Thought of Mahatma Gandhi<\/i>
\n (Oxford: Oxford University Press),<\/i> p. 69.<\/div>\n\n68. The Rudolphs,
\n op. cit., pp. 187ff.<\/p>\n<\/p><\/div>\n
\n69. Gandhi, Collected
\n Works<\/i>, vol. 13, p. 295.<\/div>\n\n70. Josef Pieper,
\n A<\/span>On the Christian
\n Idea of Man,@<\/span> cited
\n in Gilbert Meilaender, On the Theory and Practice of Virtue<\/i> (Notre
\n Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press, 1984), p. 39.<\/div>\n\n71. Ibid.<\/p><\/div>\n
\n72. Gandhi, Selected
\n Works<\/i>, vol. 4, p. 245.<\/div>\n\n73. Ibid., p. 246.<\/p><\/div>\n
\n74. Josef Pieper, The
\n Four Cardinal Virtues<\/i>, p. 147; cited in
\n <\/span>Meilaender, p. 29.<\/span><\/div>\n\n75. Robert C. Roberts,
\n "Will Power and the Virtues," Philosophical Review<\/i> (April, 1984), pp.
\n 227-247. Excerpted and extensively revised in Christina and Fred Sommers,
\n eds., Vice and Virtue in Everyday Life<\/i> (San Diego: Harcourt Brace
\n Jovanovich, 1989), p. 236.\n <\/div>\n\n
\n 76. See Khanna, p. 62n15.<\/a><\/p>\n\n\n 77. Dalai Lama,
\n <\/a>The Dalai
\n Lama at Harvard: Lectures on the Buddhist Path to Peace<\/i> (Ithaca, NY:
\n Snow Lion Publications, 1988), p. 61.<\/p>\n\n\n 78. N. D. Bhargava, "Some Chief
\n Characteristics of the Jain Concept of Nonviolence" in <\/a>
\n The
\n Contribution of Jainism to Indian Culture<\/i>, ed. R. C. Divivedi (New
\n Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1975), p. 124.<\/div>\n